There
is probably no concept more closely associated with Marx and Marxism than
class, but there is also no concept so widely misunderstood. Confusion about
class reigns at every level: in the media, in every day life and perhaps
especially in the academic world.
One
of the most common confusions is the notion that class is primarily a matter of
people’s social origins, of their position at birth, and of inherited privilege
or disadvantage. This is basically a hangover from the from the bourgeoisie’s
struggle against feudalism, when the bourgeoisie championed ‘equality’ (of
legal rights and opportunity) against inherited privileges and power of the
feudal aristocracy. It is this view that leads to the utterly mistaken idea
that class is disappearing or becoming less important in modern society (or
that America, because it was never
feudal and had no aristocracy, is somehow a classless society). Of course it is
true that inherited privilege and wealth still play an important role in the
most modern capitalism (just look at David Cameron’s cabinet of old Etonians)
but it is not the heart of the matter either for Marxist theory or in actual
social practice. It is current social position not social origin that is
crucial. The child of working class parents, who becomes manager or boss,
behaves as a manager or boss not as a worker. The young black kid who grows up
to become President of the United States behaves as the political
representative of US imperialism not the
representative of black people.
Another
widespread confusion is that class is primarily about income and/or lifestyle.
Obviously class plays a major role in determining income and lifestyle, but
neither income nor lifestyle determines class. Inequalities of wealth and
lifestyle, however wide they may be, nevertheless form a continuum from top to
bottom and therefore cannot yield a coherent analysis of the class structure.
On the basis of income or lifestyle one could conclude that there are five,
ten, or fifteen classes or none: and either way it is arbitrary. Moreover
individuals might have the same income and be members of different classes e.g.
a skilled manual worker and the owner of a small corner shop, or be members of
the same class and live very different lifestyles e.g. miners and nurses (both
part of the working class)
In
sociology, the academic discipline responsible for class, class is usually
defined in terms of different life chances (opportunities for obtaining goods
and services, for educational achievement for getting a good job, for living a
healthy and long life etc.) and the Marxist theory of class is dealt with
roughly as follows:
For
Marx, they say, class is defined by ‘relationship to the means of production’ -
leading to a two class model of society consisting of a property owning
capitalist class or bourgeoisie, and property less working class or
proletariat. There was some truth in this, but it is too simple; for the
analysis of modern society a more complex model is required and this is
provided by Max Weber and his latter day disciples. For Weber class is not just
a matter of property ownership or lack of it but of position in the labour
market. Between the capitalists and the (manual) workers there is a middle
class based on the mental skills and educational qualifications that they bring
to the job market. As capitalism becomes technologically more sophisticated
this class grows while the working class shrinks. Class polarisation fails to
materialise. Moreover there are many other divisions in society based on ‘status’
(social esteem or prestige) – contemporary Weberians would cite particularly
gender and ethnicity – which cut across class and are often more important than
class in determining people’s identity, and which Marx and Marxists have
neglected.
This
is a false account of Marx’s theory of class in many respects – Marx didn’t
have a simple two class model and was well aware of the existence of
intermediate layers, the so-called middle class, and paid a good deal more attention
to gender and race issues than Weber ever did – but this is not the key point.
The key point is that at the heart of the Marxist theory of class are not
unequal life chances (important as they are) but exploitation, the extraction
of surplus value discussed in the last section. It is the daily fact of
exploitation, the conflict of interest inherent in capitalist social relations,
that produces the capitalists and workers as antagonistic classes.
The
capitalists are those whose survival (as capitalists) depends on profit, which
derives from the surplus value obtained from wage labour. The workers are those
whose survival depends on the wages they receive for the sale of their labour
power to the capitalist. This relationship locks the former and the latter into
perpetual combat. Whether the capitalist inherited or built up his or her
capital, or went to public school or was born on a council estate, or whether
the worker earns high wages or low, works in an office or school or a factory,
or expends principally mental or physical energy does not change the essential
conflict of interest.
The
conflict of interest which has its source at the point of production extends,
like the alienation which it parallels, throughout the society which is based
on this production. It becomes a conflict of interest, a class conflict, in
every issue of state and public policy from taxation to health services to
crime and punishment, to foreign policy, arms spending, war and the
preservation of the environment.
Neither
Weber nor his sociological heirs, nor the journalists, nor the media
commentators, grasp this at all and consequently their criticism of Marx misses
its mark completely.
The
middle classes, of which they make so much, certainly exist but their position
is determined neither by their status, not their lifestyle (to repeat, status
and lifestyle are consequences not causes of class position), but by their role
in the processes of exploitation and class conflict.
Between
the bourgeoisie (the capitalist class) and the proletariat (the working class)
there are two quite large social groups. The first is the owners of small
businesses, the classical petty bourgeoisie – whose typical representative is
the small shopkeeper. This layer is oppressed by big business and even to some
extent exploited (via finance capital and the banks) but it is also, and crucially,
an exploiter of wage labour. The second group consists of managers who are paid
employees but whose function is to oversee the extraction of surplus value from
the workers. EXAMPLES
This
‘middle class’ is not really a distinct class; rather it is a hierarchy of
intermediate strata whose social role combines (in different proportions at
different levels) elements of the capitalist and elements of the proletarian
condition. At its upper end the middle class merges into the ruling class
(senior corporation managers, senior civil servants, police chiefs are
examples) and at its lower end (the self employed plumber or painter and
decorator or lower line manager) it merges into the proletariat. In the
struggle between the capitalist class and the working class the middle class
vacillates acccording to the strength of the gravitational pull of the two fundamental
classes.
In normal times, when the ruling class is
firmly in the saddle and dominating society as a whole , the middle class – in
its large majority – accepts albeit grudgingly the leadership and authority of
the upper bourgeoisie. When the grip of the ruling class weakens or goes into
crisis sections of the middle class, particularly from its lower strata, can be
won over to the side of the working class on condition that the working class
appears able to resolve the crisis in society. If the working class appears
unable to perform this role the middle classes can swing far to the right and
become the social base of fascism.
The
different understandings of class in the Marxist and the Weberian or ‘common
sense’ perspectives lead to dramatically different pictures of the class
structure in modern capitalist. Marx was emphatic that ‘In proportion as the
bourgeoisie i.e. capital, is developed, in the same proportion is the
proletariat, the modern working class developed’ and that ‘the proletarian
movement is… the movement of the immense majority in the interest of the
immense majority’ [K.Marx and F.Engels, The
Communist Manifesto in D.McLellan, as above p.226 and p. 230]
By
contrast in the Weberian/common sense view the development of capitalism leads
to a decline of the proletariat as a proportion of the population. The issue
cannot be resolved simply by counting heads because it is really a dispute
about which heads to count. For the Weberians the proletariat consists only of
‘industrial’ or ‘manual’ workers (these terms are in themselves problematic –
does not a typist work with his/her hands, does not an electrician use his/her brain?)
who are indeed shrinking in numbers in the developed capitalist countries,
while the ‘white collar’ or ‘non-manual’ employees, seen as middle class,
expand. From the Marxist standpoint, however, the majority, though not all, of
white collar employees (teachers, social workers, civil servants, typists,
sectaries, shop worker, nurses etc.) live by the sale of their labour power and
are exploited by capitalists. The exploitation of some white collar workers,
such as teachers and health workers in the public sector, is less easy to see
than that of workers who produce commodities in private industry, but what they
are really doing is producing and reproducing the commodity of labour power for
the capitalist state ie for the capitalist class and capitalist system as a
whole and like other workers they are paid less than the value of what they
produce. They are therefore part of the working class and, in practice, act as such: the PCS
(Professional Civil Servants) and the NUT (National Union of Teachers) have
been in the forefront of the recent struggles over pension rights in Britain, while teachers and tax
collectors have played an important role in the ongoing Egyptian Revolution.
Once this is grasped it is clear that the working class or proletariat continues
to constitute the large majority of the population in the developed capitalist
countries, approximately 70% or more, and is heading towards being the majority
in the world as a whole.
It
is interesting to note that whereas for most of the bourgeois views of class
the division between the working class and the middle class is seen as a
division between occupations (e.g. miners and teachers) for Marxists the
dividing line runs within occupations. Thus most teachers are workers
but head teachers are managers, most social workers are workers but (in Britain) team managers and above
are becoming middle class. In the civil service the lower ranks are working
class, but the topmost ranks are more or less part of the ruling class. It is
also interesting that, whereas most academic sociologists ignore or fail to
consider these distinctions, workers, especially trade unionists, who actually
do these jobs, are acutely aware of them.
However
for Marx the most important feature of his theory of class was his
identification of the working class’s revolutionary role. There were three
elements to this: first, the working class conflict of interest with the
capitalist class (which I have already outlined); second its power; third its
ability to create a classless society. The power of the working class derives
from the fact that its labour is the main producer of wealth and profit in
society, from the dependence of all systems of transport, energy production,
communications and all state operations in its labour, and from its
concentration in large numbers in workplaces and cities. This power gives the
working class the capacity to defeat the bourgeoisie and its state. Its
capacity to create a classless society derives from the necessarily collective
nature of its struggle (from the smallest local dispute to the widest general
strike and insurrection), from the fact that it can only take possession of the
means of production collectively, and from its potential, unlike any previous
class in history, to be both the producing and ruling class in society at the
same time, thus ending the very basis of class division.
2 comments:
Hi John. Nice to read some sanity on class, especially on a day like today, when so much nonsense is being spoken.
Having watched some very tedious programming tonight, I can't fail to celebrate what a much nicer place Britain is to live in now, than in the two decades of Thatcher onslaught, Cold War with Russia and civil war in Ireland. So as far as I'm concerned, her legacy didn't last.
Keep up the good work. And enjoy your retirement.
As usual John, when you stick to politics, you write excellently.
Glad you haven't reproduced the 'philosophical' sections of your book, which, sadly, should never have seen the light of day.
That is, given the fact that Marx waved 'goodbye' to that useless discipline in the 1840s:
"The philosophers have only to dissolve their language into the ordinary language, from which it is abstracted, in order to recognise it, as the distorted language of the actual world, and to realise that neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life." [The German Ideology.]
"One has to 'leave philosophy aside' (Wigand, p.187, cf., Hess, Die letzten Philosophen, p.8), one has to leap out of it and devote oneself like an ordinary man to the study of actuality, for which there exists also an enormous amount of literary material, unknown, of course, to the philosophers. When, after that, one again encounters people like Krummacher or 'Stirner', one finds that one has long ago left them 'behind' and below. Philosophy and the study of the actual world have the same relation to one another as onanism and sexual love." [Ibid.]
I have argued he was right to do so here (where I also show that your attempt to defend this pointless discipline fails -- do a search for you name on this page):
http://anti-dialectics.co.uk/page%2012_01.htm
Post a Comment